Versions Compared

Key

  • This line was added.
  • This line was removed.
  • Formatting was changed.

...

I first thought that Ronald Dworkin's distinction betwee~1. "fundal11.entalbetween "fundamental" and "nonfundamental" rights was only another way of l11.aking GaIuwellmaking Gamwell's distinction between "formative" and "substantive" rights. But  But I've since COl11.e come to think that this can hardly be correct-for one reasonbecause Gan1.well reason because Gamwell himself speaks of "a fundamental substantive right" (Politics as a Christian Vocation: 95; italics added). 

Anyhow, according to Michael Lynch's interpretation, 

Broadly speaking, rights can be either fundamental or not. Fundamental rights differ from other rights by being, as Ronald Dworkin has put it, matters of principle and not of policy. A right is granted CIS a matter of social policy when a protection or an advantage is accorded to a person in order to advance some desirable social goal...A fundamental right, on the other hand, is not a matter of policy...Unlike rights justified by policy, which are justified because they are means to a worthwhile social goal, fundamental rights are justified either because they are directly necessary out of basic respect due to human persons, or because they are constitutive of any political system that accords basic respect to persons. In either case, the justification for fundamental rights is seen as enormously strong, perhaps even absolute; thus the tag 'inalienable.' As Dworkin puts it, rights of this sort trump other political concerns. You can't lose them just because the majority no longer wishes to respect them.... The whole point of having a fundamental or, as it is often put, 'human right,' is that it can't justifiably be taken away just because a government suddenly decides it would be convenient to do so" (True to Life: 165 f.). 

Perhaps one way to put the matter is this: That only formative rights are to be "constitutionaly stipulated' as Gamwell maintains, does not mean that only formative rights are "fundamental," in Dworkin's sense of the term. all. the other hand, substantive rights may be "fundamental" in Dworkin's sense without being "constitutionally stipulated" along with properly formative rights as Gamwell understands them. Gamwell writes: 

Wiki Markup
Wiki Markup
Anyhow, according to Michael Lynch's interpretation,_fundamental_ _substan'tive right"_ _(Politics as a Christian Vocation:_ _95; italics added)._ _Broadly speaking, rights cCln be either fundamental or not. Fundclll1ental rights differ frorn other rights by being, as Ronald Dworkin has put it, matters of principle and not of policy. A right is granted CIS a l11.atter of social policy when a protection or an advantage is Clccorded to a person in order to Cldvance some desirable social goal. ... A fundamental right, on the other hClnd, is not a matter of policy.... Unlike rights justified by policy, which are justified because they are means to a worthwhile social goal, fundamental righ ts are justified either because they are directly necessary out of basic respect due to human persons, or because they are constitutive of Clny politicClI system that accords basic respect to persons. In either case, the justification for fundamental rights is seen ClS enormously strong, perhaps even Clbsolute; thus the tClg 'inalienable.' As Dworkin puts it, rights of this sort trump other political concerns. You can't lose them just becCluse the majority no longer wishes to respect them.... The whole point of having a fundamental or, CIS{_}{_}it_ _is often put, 'human right,' is that it can't justifiably be taken away just because a government suddenly decides it would be convenient to do so"_ _(True to Life: 165_ _f.) ._{_}Perhaps one way to put the matter is this: That only formative rights are to be "constitutionaly stipulated/' as GaIuwell Inaintains, does not mean that only fonuative rights are "fundamental," in Dworkin's sense of the tenn._{_}all._ _the other hand, substantive rights may be "fundamental" in Dworkin's sense without being "constitutionally stipulated" along with properly forn1.ative rights as Gamwell understands theln. Gamwell writes:_ _\[T\]he ultimate terms of political assessment may be restated as{_}{_}CI_ _ a fundamental substantive right: All individuals. have a right to the greatest  measure of general empowerment the state can provide or promote equa.1lyequally for el11.  all.... \[But i\]nsisting that all have a substantive right or set of rights the state  should secure is one thing, and stipulating these rights constitutionally is  something else...._ _A_ _democratic constitution_ _anticipates_ _that the full Clndand free  discourse \[it constitutes\] will be successful and thus will, through statutOlYstatutory law,  provide_ _or_ _promote for all the substantive conditions necessary to real equCllity_ _ill_ _rlw pnlirirnl prnrp"_ _it,plf npmnrr:;\]tic_ _1,()lHic\~_ _it\!>oIf_ _knot_ _,1_ _Dl.lbotnnH\'G_ _equality in the political process itself. Democratic politics itself is not a substantive possibility unless the government fulfills its moral obligation by pursuing  justice CISas general emancipation.... Because a democratic constitution_ _2{_}{_} presupposes the ultill'1ateultimate terms of political assessment, the constitution itself  implies that the principles of substantive justice are equally permanent{_}_ \[sc._ _ with those of formative justice\], even_ _if_ _it_ _does not stipulate their content (95_ _ f.) ._ _Context Jnakes 

Context makes clear, I believe, that what GmTIwell understands by_20 Novenl.ber 2007"pennanent Gamwell understands by "permanent principles" are, in Dworkin's sense, ''fundamental principles." In any In any case, Gan1well Gamwell removes any doubt that substantive principles of justice are justice are "equally pernl.anentpermanent" with its formative principles

20 November 2007 

"fundal11.ental" and "nonfundamental" rights was only another way of 
l11.aking GaIuwell's distinction between "formative" and "substantive" rights. 
But I've since COl11.e to think that this can hardly be correct-for one reason 
because Gan1.well himself speaks of "a fundamental substan'tive right" 
(Politics as a Christian Vocation: 95; italics added). "fundamental" and "nonfundamental" rights was only another way of making Gamwell's distinction between "formative" and "substantive" rights. But I've since come to think that this can hardly be correct-for one reason because Gamwell himself speaks of "a fundamental substantive right" (Politics as a Christian Vocation: 95; italics added).