Versions Compared

Key

  • This line was added.
  • This line was removed.
  • Formatting was changed.

SCANNED PDF

On Rorty's Historicist PhiIosophy* 

1.. As much as I agree with Rorty's criticism of the position of Pinker, Wilson, et al.—to the effect that no results of empirical science can provide what religious and philosophical theories of human nature were traditionally looked to to provide, i.e., normative guidance in the form of "a vision of the good life or of the good society" (19)—1 can't even begin to agree with the position he would presumably put in its place. One reason for this is that what appears from this essay to be his inventory of the relevant possible means for obtaining reliable knowledge is incomplete in mentioning only: (1) "empirical scientific inquiry"; (2)''uninformed common sense"; andand (3) "a priori philosophizing" (21). So far as I'm concerned, at any rate, there's at s at least a fourth additional alternative that could be called "transcendental metaphysics transcendental metaphysics (as including, in its broad sense, "existentialist analysis")." Nothing  Nothing that Rorty says in criticizing the other alternatives seems to me in the in the least telling against this further alternative, especially as compared with his own his own "historicist" position. Another  Another reason why I can't agree with him is thatis that, if what can be learned from empirical science cannot be reasonably substituted reasonably substituted for traditional philosophy and religion, the same is true of his own his own proposed substitution of "what we can only learn from history-the record history—the record of past intellectual and social experiments," or, as he also puts it, "historical narrative and utopian speculation" (20, 23). "History" in the sense of sense of an empirical-historical record or narrative of the past is as little able as empirical as empirical science to provide normative guidance. And whether or not such such "utopian speculation," or "dreaming," as Rorty also calls it, can really provide guidance provide guidance rather than simply leading us up the garden path depends on whether on whether or not it's, in its own way, valid. But, of course, to establish that it is, even  even as to provide any norm for learning anything normative from history, is hardly to be distinguished from developing something very like a theory of human of human nature, or, at the least, a philosophical anthropology. 

2. Rorty speaks of the "historicist turn" effected, presumably, by those he those he calls "historicist philosophers like Ortega" (23, 19). My guess is that he's probably s probably right in interpreting "philosophers like Ortega" as he does: as in no way no way saying or meaning that humans are "blank slates," but as only doubting or doubting or denying that any source-whether source—whether religion, philosophy, or science-can

2

give science—can give us anything appropriately called "a theory of human nature," which is to sayto say, a "normative" theory that provides "guidance," that tells us "what to do with do with ourselves," or "what sort of people we ought to become" (18). But

Wiki Markup
_3. Rorty evidently sets great store by what he calls "the conversations among humanists about alternative self-images and alternative ideals" (23;_{_}As much as I agree with Rorty's criticism of the position of Pinker, Wilson,_ _et al.-to_ _the effect that no results of empirical science can provide what religious and philosophical theories of human nature were traditionally looked to to provide, i.e., normative guidance in the form of "a vision of the good life or of the good society" (19)-1 can't even begin to agree with the position he would presumably put in its place. One reason for this is that what appears from this essay to be his inventory of the relevant possible means for obtaining reliable knowledge is incomplete in mentioning only:_ _if_ _one asks why "historicist philosophers" hold this, the only answer one gets from Rorty is, simply, "Because they do," because, for them, "there is nothing we essentially are" (19). They simply hold that, although "there are many lessons to be learned from history, there is "no superlesson to be learned from science, or religion, or philosophy" (19). Thus Rorty's own argument against what he calls "\[t\]he unfortunate idea that philosophy could detect the difference between nature and convention-between what is essential to being a human being and what is merely a product of historical circumstance" is not at all systematic but is entirely historical. He doesn't say that the idea is "false," however clearly he may imply this, but only that it is "unfortunate"; and whether this characterization is by way of giving a reason for its subsequent post-Enlightenment fall into "deserved disrepute," or only another way of describing its fate remains unclear._ _In_ _any case, that a certain notion has, "in the last two centuries," fallen into "disrepute" in no way establishes that it "deserved" to do so, and yet Rorty gives not the least nonquestion-begging, or non-self-serving, reason for thinking that_ _it_ _did. So, too, the fact, assuming it is such, that "\[t\]he idea, shared by Plato and Rousseau, that there is such a thing as_ _the_ _good life for man has gradually been replaced by the conviction that there are_ _many_ _equally valuable human lives" provides not the least reason for thinking that the conviction replacing the idea is valid (19)._ _In_ _sum:_ _if_ _Rorty ever gives any_ _systematic_ _reasons for the things he obviously holds and wants to advance, I've missed them; and his mere descriptions of what may have, in fact, happened in history are as irrelevant to the important systematic question of justification as anything could possibly be._ _cf._ _22, where he speaks of "the roles previously played by philosophers and other humanists-roles such as critic of culture, moral guide, guardian of rationality, and prophet of the new utopia"). But, so far as I can see, he says nothing to meet the objection, which he himself mentions, that, whereas "scientists have knowledge," "humanists only have opinions" (22). In other_ _3{_}{_}words, his "conversations" are, at most, exchanges of opinions (or-to use one of his own favorite terms-"convictions"), or,_

 But if one asks why "historicist philosophers" hold this, the only answer one gets from Rorty is, simply, "Because they do," because, for them, "there is nothing we essentially are" (19). They simply hold that, although "there are many lessons to be learned from history, there is "no superlesson to be learned from science, or religion, or philosophy" (19). Thus Rorty's own argument against what he calls "[t]he unfortunate idea that philosophy could detect the difference between nature and convention—between what is essential to being a human being and what is merely a product of historical circumstance" is not at all systematic but is entirely historical. He doesn't say that the idea is "false," however clearly he may imply this, but only that it is "unfortunate"; and whether this characterization is by way of giving a reason for its subsequent post-Enlightenment fall into "deserved disrepute," or only another way of describing its fate remains unclear. In any case, that a certain notion has, "in the last two centuries," fallen into "disrepute" in no way establishes that it "deserved" to do so, and yet Rorty gives not the least non­-question-begging, or non-self-serving, reason for thinking that it did.  So, too, the fact, assuming it is such, that "[t]he idea, shared by Plato and Rousseau, that there is such a thing as the good life for man has gradually been replaced by the conviction that there are many equally valuable human lives" provides not the least reason for thinking that the conviction replacing the idea is valid (19). In sum: if Rorty ever gives any systematic reasons for the things he obviously holds and wants to advance, I've missed them; and his mere descriptions of what may have, in fact, happened in history are as irrelevant to the important systematic question of justification as anything could possibly be.

3. Rorty evidently sets great store by what he calls "the conversations among humanists about alternative self-images and alternative ideals" (23; cf. 22, where he speaks of "the roles previously played by philosophers and other humanists—roles such as critic of culture, moral guide, guardian of rationality, and prophet of the new utopia"). But, so far as I can see, he says nothing to meet the objection, which he himself mentions, that, whereas "scientists have knowledge," "humanists only have opinions" (22). In other words, his "conversations" are, at most, exchanges of opinions (or—to use one of his own favorite terms"—convictions"), or, if you will, occasions for mutual 4. Notwithstanding that Rorty's whole way of arguing is merelyif you will, occasions for mutual witnessing, as distinct from anything at all like proper "discourses," or  or rational arguments. He has good reason, then, for preferring his term term "convictions" to "theories" (dcf. 21), and the most he can talk about is the the "change," or "modification,"of our convictions, as distinct from anything like anything like their argumentative validation. 

4. Notwithstanding that Rorty's whole way of arguing is merely descriptive, he continually makes or implies normative judgments that he in no in no way justifies, since they logically cannot be justified on merely descriptive, historical  historical grounds. Thus, for example, he says that traditional theories of human of human nature were "very useful" because "they suggested perils to avoid and ideals and ideals to serve," and so "marketed helpful moral and political advice," even if if "in fancy, disposable, packaging" (18 f.). But But, clearly, whether or not such advice such advice was really "useful" or "helpful" depends on whether or not the assertions the assertions underlying it, or implied by it, are or are not valid assertions. Or Or, again again, he says that our convictions about what really matters "need not-and should not-take not—and should not—take the form of a theory of human nature, or a theory of anything of anything else" (21). But what, one wants to ask, justifies this "should not"? The  The answer is not made easier by Rorty's odd way of talking about our convictions our convictions "taking the form of a theory" and by his caricature of critical validationcritical validation's being a matter of deducing our convictions from a theory. In point In point of fact, it's a matter of verifying the assertions that supply the content of our of our convictions by the procedures appropriate to verifying assertions of that logical that logical kind. And holding that such assertions as are thus verified comprise a proper a proper theory is something rather different from saying anything about the corresponding convictions somehow taking the form of a theory. But be this as· this as it may, if Rorty's point is that our convictions about what really matters not matters not only need not but also should not be critically validated, he says nothing whatever nothing whatever in support of his point. And the same is true of his implication that that "cultural evolution," being on a par with "biological evolution," is "equally capable equally capable of creating something radically new and better" (23). "Better," clearly, is a normative concept. But where does Rorty ever clearly state and argue for the for the validity of the norm that he necessarily implies in so applying it? For all he all he shows to the contrary, the most he can claim, consistently with his own 4historicist own historicist premises, is that, by his "convictions," or those of some other other 
individual or community, the something that cultural evolution is capable of creating of creating is not only radically new but "better"

*All page references are to Richard Rorty, "Philosophy-envy,"

(cf. 19, where he speaks of "our present conviction that the best sociopolitical setup is one in which individuals are free to live whichever of these [sc. many equally valuable human] lives they choose"). 

*All page references are to Richard Rorty, "Philosophy-envy," Dædalus, 133,4 (Fall 2004): 18-24. 

30 November 2004  Wiki Markup_30 November 2004{_}_(d._ _19, where he speaks of "our present conviction that the best sociopolitical setup is one in which individuals are free to live whichever of these_ _\[sc._ _many equally valuable human\] lives they choose")._ _Dcedalus,_ _133,4 (Fall 2004): 18-24._