Versions Compared

Key

  • This line was added.
  • This line was removed.
  • Formatting was changed.

SCANNED PDF


What are the promise and the limitations, if any, of Habermas's critical theory for "a theology of the public realm"?

...

4. Philosophical theory in general and Habermas's critical theory in particular can both be promising and have limitations with resepct respect to theology or its task, because, while theology has to do its own thinking and speaking and cannot delegate even the least part of it to any nontheological field, discipline, or specialty, including philosophy, theological problemsespeciaUy problems—especially the most fundamental such problems-are problems—are not only theological problems; and theological solutions, accordingly, have to be, in at least some important respects, not only theological solutions. Insofar as theology thinks and speaks about human existence, and therefore human praxis, culture, and history, its problems in doing so are, in the nature of the case, philosophical as well as theological problems. Similarly, because theological thinking and speaking have to be credible to human existence as well as appropriate to Jesus Christ, its solutions to its problems have to be philosophical as well as theological solutions. In other words, although theology's problems are its own, and although it has to do its own thinking and speaking in trying to solve them, theology can and should think with philosophy's resources as well as its own in reaching its solutions-provided solutions—provided always that its solutions, exactly like its problems, are really its own.

5. But now the second question that has to be answered in order to answer the main question is, What, exactly, is to be understood by the phrase, "a theology of the public realm"? Given that, being a genitive phrase, it is systematically ambiguous, how is it to be understood-as a understood—as an objective genitive or as an a subjective genitive?

6. I contend that it should be understood in both senses. Insofar as it is understood as an objective genitive, it means a properly theological reflection that has the public realm as its object. On the other hand, insofar as it is understood as a subjective genitive, it means a theology that is not only in the public realm, but also of it, in that it is a reflection that takes place in accordance with the same relevant standards of reflection that prevail in the public realm generally.

...

7. I think one can reasonably argue that Habermas's critical theory, like critical theory generally, is promising and has limitations with respect to a theology of the public realm in both senses of the phrase. As for its being promising with respect to a theology of the public realm in the first (objective) sense, this seems to me to lie in its being, as it were, a thick description of human existence, and thus of human praxis, culture, and history in general as well as of the present human situation in particular. Its limitation in this respect, in my opinion, is its failure adequately to account for the properly existential question as an irreducible human question, fundamental to, and therefore both related to, and distinct from, the other basic human questions concerning the true, the right, and the beautiful. At this point, it has to be supplemented by analyses like Schleiermacher's, of religion as neither knowing nor acting but feeling; or Tillich's, of religion as ultimate concern; or Rahner's, of human existence as in principle self-transcendence into absolute mystery; or Hartshorne's, of religion as worship, or what any selfunderstanding self-understanding individual does with her or his fragmentariness relative to the integral, all-encompassing whole of reality as such, and so on. This means, among other things, that Habermas's metaphysical or philosophical anthropology can and should be supplemented by a metaphysical or philosophical theology and cosmology, as well as by a general metaphysical ontology.

...