Versions Compared

Key

  • This line was added.
  • This line was removed.
  • Formatting was changed.

SCANNED PDF

On Transcendentals

A concept is said to be "transcendent" in later scholastic philosophy insofar as it goes beyond the limits of any and all class concepts, including categories, and therefore applies to literally everything without restriction. Such concepts are called "transcendentals" (= transcendentia, or transcendentalia) and are usually understood to include "being," or "a being" (= ens = das Seiende, or die Seiendheit), "thing" (= res = das Ding, or die Washeit = die Sachlichkeit), "something" (= aliquid = das Etwas, or die Etwasheit, i.e., die Abgegrenztheit gegenüber jedes andere), "one" (= unum = das Eine, or die Einheit, i.e., die innere Untrennbarkeit der

...

wesentlichen Bestimmungen), "true" (= verum = das Wahre, or die Wahrheit = die Erkennbarkeit  = die Geistbezogenheit), "good" (= bonum = das Gute, or die Werthaftigkeit = die Erstrebbarkeit = die Willensbezogenheit). Sometimes, especially in the Fransiscan schools, there was added "beauty" (= pulchrum = das

...

Schöne, or die

...

Schönheit, i.e., die

...

mühlosselbstverständliche Übereinstimmung mit dem Anschauungsvermögen). Because all of these concepts have the same completely unrestricted scope as the concept "being," they are all said to be "convertible" with it, and it with them. 

In later scholastic and neoscholastic philosophy, the term "transcendental" often has the same meaning as the term "transcendent," i.e., going beyond the limits of all classes and kinds, and hence all univocal meaning, to analogy. Hence "transcendentia" are also called_" {} transcendentalia." _

Kant gives the term "transcendental" a new, distinctively different meaning when he calls all knowledge "transcendental" insofar as it has to do, not with objects, but with our way of knowing objects, to the extent that such knowledge is possible a priori. Thus "transcendental" does not designate something that goes beyond experience--for experience—for that, Kant simply uses "transcendent"--but —but rather something prior to experience that nonetheless has no purpose other than to make knowledge based on experience possible. Accordingly, the contrasting term to "transcendental," as he uses it, is "empirical." 

...

Of especial interest so far as my own metaphysical reflections are concerned is the doctrine of transcendentia developed by Duns Scotus. For him, the passiones entis (= attributes of being) include both passiones e. convertibiles, such as one, true, and good, and passiones e. disjunctæ, such as necessary/contingent (sc. possible) and act/potency, both of which are "transcendent" attributes. Moreover, the concept "being," and thus the concepts of its attributes, are univocal, in the sense that they belong to being either "as indifferent to finite and [infinite]," in the case of the convertible attributes," or as including both finite and infinite, act and potency, and so on, in the case of the disjunctive attributes. 

September 1981; rev. 22 July 2002