The Notebooks of Schubert Ogden

You are viewing an old version of this page. View the current version.

Compare with Current View Page History

« Previous Version 5 Next »

SCANNED PDF

On the Distinction between "Being-in-Itself" and "Meaning-for-Us"  

1.  Analysis  discloses  that  "real"  and  its  cognates  are  systematically  ambig­uous,  in  that,  while  it has  a  "field-invariant  force,"  it has  "field-depend­ent  standards."  This  is  not  surprising,  of  course,  because  the  same  syste­matic  ambiguity  attends  "true"  and  its  cognates,  with  which  "real"  and  its cognates  are  correlative.  For  this  reason;  then,  one  could  say  that  the  dis­tinction  between  "being-in-itself"  and  "meaning-for-us"  is  misleading,  insofar as  it implies,  or  appears  to  imply,  that  "reality"  is  not  thus  systematically ambiguous,  and  hence  field-dependent  as  well  as  field-invariant. 

1.  Analysis discloses that  "real" and  its cognates are  systematically  ambig­uous,  in  that,  while  it has  a  "field-invariant  force,"  it has  "field-depend­ent  standards."  This is not surprising,  of  course,  because  the  same  systematic  ambiguity  attends  "true"  and  its  cognates,  with  which "real"  and  its cognates  are  correlative.  For  this  reason;  then,  one  could  say  that  the  dis­tinction  between  "being-in-itself"  and  "meaning-for-us"  is misleading,  insofar as  it implies,  or  appears  to  imply,  that  "reality"  is  not  thus  systematically ambiguous,  and  hence  field-dependent  as  well  as field-invariant.

2.  But  this  is  in  no  way  to  say  that  there  is  not  a  difference  within  any given  field  between  what  is  real  and  what  is  not.  For  if what  is  real,  given some  mode  of  reasoning,  some  way  of  taking  account  of  things  that  we  are  in one  way  or  another  obliged  to  take  account  of,  is,  indeed,  relative  to  this mode  of  reasoning,  this  way  of  taking  account  of  things,  it is  not  in  the  least relative  to  any  particular  conclusion  arrived  at within  this  mode  of  reasoning or  way  of  taking  account  of  things.  In  other  words,  there  remains  the  distinc­tion  between  what  is  believed  to  be  true,  given  this  mode  of  reasoning,  and what  is  worthy  of  being  believed  true, given  the  standards  established  by  this same  mode  of  reasoning.  In  this  sense,  one  could  say  that  the  distinction between  "being-in-itself"  and  "meaning-for-us"  is  both  pertinent  and  important, insofar  as  it expresses,  or  is  taken  to  express,  that  what  is  worthy  of  being believed  is  one  thing,  what  in  fact  is  believed,  something  irreducibly  different. 

3.  It would  appear  clear  enough,  then,  that)however  religious  utterances  rep­resent  a  mode  of  reasoning,  or  a  way  of  taking  account  of  what  we  are  somehow obliged  to  take  account  of,  within  that  mode  or  way  there  is  a  distinction  be­tween  what  is  worthy  of  being  believed  and  what  in  fact  is  believed,  and  hence sufficient  reason  to  employ  the  distinction  between  "being-in-itself"  and "meaning-for-us."  It would  appear  to  be  no  less  clear  that  no  religious  ut­terance  could  be  said  to  be  true  that  did  not  speak  about  the  reality  it pur­ports  to  be  about  not  only  in  its meaning  for-us  but  also  in  its  being-in­itself--not  only  as  what  we  in  fact  believe,  but  also  as  what  is  worthy  of our  belief,  whether  we  in  fact  believe  it or  not. 

4.  But  this  still  leaves  open  the  question  of  the  mode  of  reasoning,  or  way of  taking  account  of  things  that  must  somehow  be  taken  account  of  within  which religious  utterances  are  either  true  or  false.  The  answer  to  this  question can  be  given  only  by  rightly  locating  the  religious  mode  of  reasoning,  or  way of  taking  account  of  reality,  relative  to  the  metaphysical  mode  of  reasoning, on  the  one  hand,  and  the  moral  mode  of  reasoning,  on  the  other.  (I  can't see my  way  clear  to  doing  this  rightly  here.  The  essential  point  is  that,  while the  religious  mode  of  reasoning  overlaps,  and  hence  necessarily  presupposes both  the  metaphysical  and  the  moral  modes,  religious  utterances  nevertheless are  neither  properly  metaphysical  nor  properly  moral.  This  means,  among  other things,  that  religious  utterances  as  such as distinct from the metaphysical and moral assertions they necessarily implyclaim  to  be  expressions  of  the authentic  self-understanding  whose  possibility  is  implied  both  by  a  true  meta­physics and  a  just morality. Thus,  while  they  make  or  imply  claims  about self,  others,  and  the  whole,  they  do  so  only  as  authorizing the  self-understanding  that  they  also  express.  So  far  as  the  reli­gious  mode  of  reasoning  as  such  is  concerned,  then,  "God"  in  its proper  theis­tic,  as  distinct  from  its  broader,  religious,  meaning  refers  to  the  universal individual  as  authorizing  a  self-understanding  of  radical  trust  and  radical loyalty.  To  affirm,  accordingly,  "I  believe  in  God,"  is  to  affirm  not  only that  one  in  fact  does  believe  in  God  but  also  that  one  in  principle  ought  to believe  in  God  even  if one  does  not  in  fact  do  so,  because  God  gives  and  de­mands  just such  faith.  By  comparison,  then,  with  the  way  in  which  metaphys­ics  takes  account  of  God,  one  could  say,  quite  understandably,  religious  ut­terances  have  to  do  with  the  meaning-of-God-for-us,  not  with  the  being-of-God­in-itself.  But  this  would  neither  imply  the  illegitimacy  in  principle  of metaphysical  talk  about  God  (on  the  ground  that  it mistakenly  tries  to  over­come  the  systematic  ambiguity  of  IIreal,.'  etc.) nor collapse  the  crucial  distinc­tion  between  what  is  believed  and  what  is  worthy  of  belief.  It would  simply make  clear  the  important  difference  between  religion  and  metaphysics.  And  so, too,  one  could  show,  with  the  no  less  important  difference  between  the  reli­gious  mode  of  reasoning  and  the  moral. 

5. An  analogy  may  be  useful.  The  criteria  appropriate  for  common  sense  talk about  what  is  real  allows  one  to  say  of  the  sun  at sunset  that  it is  "really red."  To  deny  that  such  talk  is  about  the  real,  on  the  ground  that  yet  other criteria require  one  to  say  that  the  sun  at  sun­set  is  "really  yellow"  is  simply  to  shift  the  discussion  to  another  mode  of reasoning.  What  the  religious  mode  of  reasoning  means  by  ultimate  reality  is what  confronts  us  with  the  possibility  of  authentic  self-understanding.  To deny  that  the  talk  involved  in  the  religious  mode  of  reasoning  is  about  the real,  on  the  ground  that  yet  other  criteria-those of the metaphysician, say, ­require  one  to  say  that  ultimate  reality  is  the  universal  individual  that  is the  ground  and  end  of  all  other  individuals  and  events,  etc.,  is,  again,  sim­ply  to  shift  the  discussion  to another  mode  of  reasoning.

6. The  christological  payoff  of  all  this  can  be  put  very  briefly.  If  the sub­ject  of  the  constitutive  christological  assertion  is  a  constant,  the predicate is avariable  that  has  had  and  can  have  any  number  of  values.  Whatever  its values,  however,  the  function  of  the  variable  is  to  affirm  of the  subject that  it is  the  decisive  revelation  of  God  in  the  sense  of  explicitly  author­izing  the  authentic  self-understanding  that  God  implicitly authorizes  in  and and through  all  human  experience.  But  this  means,  then,  that  christological  ut­terances  are  a  special  class  of  utterances representing  the  religious  mode of  reasoning.  As  such,  they  intend  to  talk  about  the  real  in  its  being-in­ itself  as  well  as  in  its meaning-for-us, insofar  as  they  express  not  only what  in  fact  is  believed  concerning  the  subject  of  the  christological  asser­tion,  but  also  what  in  principle  ought to  be  believed,  whether  it in  fact  is believed  or  not.  At  the  same  time,  they,  too,  are  personal  address,  indirect if  not  direct,  in  that  they  are  at one  and  the  same  time  statements  about Christ  and  about  myself,  about  my  own  authentic  possibility. By  comparison with metaphysical statements,  then,  they  can  be  said  to  be  about  the  meaning­ of-Christ-for-us,  not  about  the  being-of-Christ-in-himself. 

2 July 1980

1.  On  the  one  hand,  to  hold,  as  I  do,  that  it is  important  to  talk  about the  being  of  God  in  itself  as  well  as  the  meaning  of  God  for  us  may  appear  to deny  that  all  talk  about  the  being  of  God,  as  of  the  being  of  anything  else, takes  place  in  terms  of  some  field(s)  of  discourse,  established  by  some  possi­ble  human  question(s)  and  concern(s).--This,  however,  I  have  no  intention  of denying,  because  I  entirely  agree  that  meaningful  talk  about  the  being  of  any­thing  is  relative  to  some  presupposed  mode  of  reasoning;  and  I  insist  that  one can  agree  with  this  without  being  a  metaphysical  neutralist.

 2.  On  the  other  hand,  to  hold,  as  Bultmann  does,  that  it  is  illegitimate  to talk  about  the  being  of  God  in  itself  as  well  as  the  meaning  of  God  for  us  may appear  to  deny  that  all  talk  about  God,  like  any  other  talk  purporting  to  ex­press  truth,  presupposes  the  distinction  between  what  is  worthy  of  being  be­lieved  and  what  in  fact  is  believed.--This,  however,  Bultmann  hardly  has  any intention  of  denying,  because  he  entirely  agrees  that  there  is,  indeed,  a  nec­essary  distinction  between  what  is  true  and  what  is  believed  with  respect  to God,  etc. 

3.  Clearly,  then,  there  need  be  no  contradiction  between  our  two  positions. 

23  July  1980 

1.  Bultmann's  thesis  is  correct  that  talk  of  God  is  strictly  existential,  in  that  it is  always  talk  about  the  meaning  of  God  for  us. 

2.  But  strictly  existential  talk  has  two  aspects--metaphysical  and  moral. The  first  has  to  do  with  the  necessary  conditions  of  the  possibility  of  our existence  and  of  all  existence;  while  the  second  has  to  do  with  the  authentic possibility  of  our  existence  for  acting  responsibly  in  relation  to  all  other existence.  The  essential  point  about  existential  talk  is  that  these  two  as­pects  are  mutually  determining--our  authentic  possibility  being  the  mode  of existence  appropriate to ultimate  reality,  and  conversely  (Geertz). 

3.  Because  this  is  so,  one  can  indeed  say  that  theology  must  be  able  to  speak of  God  in  his  being  in  himself  as  well  as  of  God  in  his  meaning  for  us.  But, in  saying  this,  one  should  be  clear  that  one  is  not  talking  either  about  two different  things  or  about  two  (abstract)  aspects  of  one  thing  but  about  one of  the  two  (abstract)  aspects  of  one  thing  (namely,  its metaphysical  aspect) and  this  one  thing  itself  (namely,  existential  talk  about  God).

3  May  1979 

  • No labels