The Notebooks of Schubert Ogden

You are viewing an old version of this page. View the current version.

Compare with Current View Page History

« Previous Version 2 Current »

SCANNED PDF

  1. Experience is always experience
  2. Thought, or, as may also be said, understanding or reason, is always part of an experience and therefore is always thought
  3. More exactly, thought is always about reality, not in its concrete content, quality, or value, but in its more or Jess abstract structure. Insofar as reality in its concrete content, quality, or value is given to us at aU, it is not given through thought but through experience, although our experience itself is, in its way, so fragmentary and abstract as to mediate concrete reality only very inadequately. 0]-"-of reaHty as given to, and independent of, our experience. about-about the reality given to, and independent of, our experience. 
  1. A ny concrete reality has a content, quality, or value in itself as well as for Clil other concrete realities experiencing it or otherwise internally related to it; and it may also have a meaning for us as beings who not only experience
  2. But if any concrete reality has a content, quality, or vaJue in itself as well as for others, and may also have a meaning for us, it also has a structure in itself, which, relative to the concrete reality as such, is abstract, offering different abstract aspects in which it but also understand and think about what we experience. This meaning it has, however, not in its intrinsic value as a concrete reality but in its different abstract aspects, and thus in its constitutive or instrumental value for us. it may be of constitutive or instrumental value for us. 

6. Thought ubout reality, as distinct from experience of reality, is always either thought aboutuitinUlte reality (including strictly ultimate reality) as mediated by our experience in its vertical dinlension or existe1ltial aspect, in which case it is properly distinguished as metaphysics; or thought about immediate reality as mediated by our experience in its other horizontal dimension or empirical aspect, in which case it is properly said to be scie1lce, i.e., one or the other of the so-called special sciences. 

  1. Thought takes place on two closely related but clearly distinguishable levels: on the primary level of self-understanding and life-praxis; and on the secondary level of critical reflection! appropriation and proper theory.
  2. Thought on the primary level is already involved in normal adult "experience," which is as truly thought about reality as it is experience of reality. On this primary level, thought consists in asking and answering our various vital questions, existential and also intellectual, thereby making or implying certain clailTIs to va1idity. 

Thought on the secondary level, by contrast, consists in critically reflecting on/appropriating our thought and experience on the primary leveL Specifically, critical reflection/ appropriation includes bothcritical illte111retatioll of the answers to our various vital questions, existential and also inteJlectual, and crillcaivaiidatioll of the claims we make or imply in answering them as we do. In other words, the questions we ask and answer on the secondary level are not the various vital questions we ask and answer on the primary level, but rather the tlzeoretiLlll questions of meaning and validity-not simply as such, of course, but as oriented by, and corresponding to, our various vital questions. 

Still another word closely related to "thought," along with "understanding" and "reason," is "belief." And what has been said so far about thought, understanding, and reason may also be said,mutatis mutalldis, about belief. Thusr for example, if we may say that thought about reality on the primary level is already a part of normal aduH "experience" of reality, we may say the same concerning belief, because our ordinary "experience" of reality is shot through with beliefs about it. Or, again, we may and must distinguish our various vital beliefs on the primary level from our corresponding theoretical beliefs on the secondary level. 

In the same way, we may and must distinguish between our basic beliefs about uHimate reality as mediated by our experience in its vertical dimension or existential aspect and all of our.other beliefs about immediate reality that necessarilypresuppose our basic beliefs, but that are themselves mediated by our experience in its other dimension or aspect previously distinguished as horizontal or empirical.

  1. If, then, the claims to truth that we make or imply for our beliefs are valid, this can only be because our beliefs about reality, like our understandings of it, or our thoughts and reasonings about it, agree with, or correspond to, reality as it is. And the,only conceivable test, finally, of whether this necessary condition is satisfied is that our beliefs, or the assertions that we believe to be true, may somehow claim the support of our experience of reality: of the vertical dimension or existential aspect of our experience, in the case of our basic beliefs; and of the horizontal dimension or elnpirical aspect of our experience, in the case of our other beliefs. This is the only conceivable test, finally, because the abstract aspects or structure of concrete realities with which our beliefs, thoughts, understandings, and reasonings about them must agree, or to which they must correspond, in order to be true are mediated only by our experience of concrete realities in one or the other of its two dimensions or aspects.In addition to the connections among the several distinctions previously clarified--experience and thought, concrete and abstract, mystery and inteIJigibility-there is also the connection between all of them and the distinction between the divine and the nondivine. This distinction, however, does not paralJel the others but cuts across them, in that the divine and the nondivine can each be said to be, in infinitely, qualitatively different ways, objects of both experience and thought and to have aspects in themselves that are both concrete and abstract, both content and structure, and both mystery and intelligibility. "The infinite, qualitative difference" between the divine and the nondivine is the difference between "all" and "some" (in contrast to "none"), or "whole" and "part." Thus, while the divine, like the nondivine, is an object of both experience and thought, it is properly distinguished asthe object, the universal and all-indusive object thereof, even as the nondivine is simply all object, a particular and partially exclusive object among many others, both of experience and of thought. Or, again, the divine qua concrete and abstract, or in its content and also its structure, is not simply a concrete or content, or all abstract or structure, but is the concrete or content and the abstract or structure. This is because the divine as all or the whole includes within itself as concrete or content all other nondivine concretes or contents, even as in its aspect as abstract or structure it is included within all other abstracts or structures as well as all other concretes or contents. In the same way, or for the same reason, the divine qua concrete or content is not simply a mystery, but tlze mystery, alJ mystery compounded into one allencompassing, impenetrable mystery, while qua abstract or structure, the divine is not siInply all intelligible, but is the intelligible, all intelJigibility united into one incOlnparably lucid abstract or structure. 
    23 August 1999; rev. 10 September 2005; 2 February 2010
  • No labels